[MD] All the way down
Matt Kundert
pirsigaffliction at hotmail.com
Wed Dec 15 11:22:33 PST 2010
Steve formulated "psychological nominalism" as:
[B] Language use is a process of relating things to other things, but
language never bottoms out. The things that are being related by
language are bits of language to other bits of language. Rather than
knowledge being a matter of finding the proper correspondences
between sentences and non-language, such linguistic relations go all
the way down. The test of truth for a knowledge claim is then not
correspondence with non-linguistic reality but the consequences of
believing or disbelieving a claim.
Matt:
Whether Pirsig needs to deny [B] is a good way of stating the
problem, I think. And I do not think there is any need for Pirsig to
deny [B], though I think if you were to personally ask him, he might.
However, if one made the right kind of vocabulary massages, I'm
not sure there's an important problem.
The first objection will be to the restriction of the word "knowledge"
to something that only comes in linguistic form (as "claims"). Pirsig
once formulated this using Russell's notion of "knowledge by
acquaintance." However, as a way of pulling together epistemology
and linguistics, some philosophers have argued against it as, in
essence, a version of one of Quine's two dogmas of empiricism or
Sellars' Myth of the Given. This is not an implication Pirsig intends.
What Pirsig intends, I think (and only in one manner), is a distinction
between non-linguistic know-how and linguistic knowing-that, such
that I know how to ride a bicycle even if I couldn't tell you verbally
how.
There is no reason for psychological nominalists to deny the
distinction between know-how and knowing-that, and in fact, if
Robert Brandom is right, they couldn't and still get off the ground a
working philosophy of language.
The other route of rapprochement is to highlight the similarity
between Quine's picture of a "field of force whose boundary
conditions are experience" (that I quoted in the post "Quine on
Experience") and Pirsig's picture of static patterns surrounded by
DQ in SODV. And then one merely needs to highlight Quine's "field
as a whole" addendum, Pirsig's "only people respond to DQ" clause,
and compare it to Marsha's recent treatment of static patterns as
both useful and a delusion, and I think you have how to put the two
together. The whole of our static patterns interact with this
undefinable thing called "experience" (DQ), and the interaction as a
whole itself can only be described in vague metaphors like "fields of
force" and "pointing at the moon" and "looking through tears in the
map at the ground below." And if you focus in on just the patterns,
then you can further delineate two ways in which we interact with
the experience: know-how (inorganic/bio/social) and knowing-that
(intellectual).
The nice thing about the route analytic philosophy has taken in the
last 100 years is that they'd isolated on knowing-that, and that now,
100 years later, we can see clearly--partly through the dialectical
process of the analytic philosophers themselves--how to reject all
the metaphysical baloney people like Russell attached to notions like
"knowledge by acquaintance" and describe the process of
knowing-that better than we ever have before, without the attendant
notion that that's all we need to do. Somebody like Brandom would
never presume to say that all one needs to know can be found in his
tome, Making It Explicit, though Wittgenstein came near saying
something like that at the end of the Tractatus. Brandom is just a
specialist, and analytic philosophy just a specialty, to be used for
certain kinds of things.
Matt
More information about the Moq_Discuss
mailing list