[MD] brief tangent with Steve
Matt Kundert
pirsigaffliction at hotmail.com
Tue Dec 21 15:53:15 PST 2010
Hi Dave,
Dave said:
To say James's theory is only about justification and not about truth
is to assert a certain definition of truth, one that says that truth is
something over and above justification. ... But James
re-conceptualized the meaning of truth such that it can only ever be
what's justified in experience.
Steve said:
Rorty's conception of truth is not a something which can be over and
above something else. He just supports the notion of making a
distinction between truth and justification. He preserves the common
sense notion and usage of the word "true" in that what we are
justified in believing may not be true.
Matt:
Steve is pointing out there the funny move on your part, Dave. You
say the above because you're asserting that Rorty's rejection of
"theories of truth" is based on a Platonism-defined opponent. That's
right: if there is ever any rejection, it is only because of a prior act of
accepting for polemical purposes the opponent's terms of debate.
You also then like to say, "Why not reject the definition?" Rorty does
this also. When he moves to this part of his project, that's when it
helps to not take so seriously his polemical slogans. What Steve is
pointing out is that Rorty's agreement with a semantic definition of
truth distinguishes between truth and justification, but does not take
one to be "higher" than another. That means you're actually the
one importing the "false dilemma" in your first sentence above.
Further, the question for James's re-conceptualization that you've
articulated is: can we not ever have a true belief that isn't justified?
If I believe that you're holding a Jack of Spades in your hand right
now, what possible justification might that belief have? However,
if it was _true_ that you, Dave Buchanan, for whatever reason,
were holding a Jack of Spades in your hand as you read this
e-mail, I would have a true belief. This is the kind of thought
experiment that illustrates to some people that "true" and
"justified" have two different semantic roles, _and_ that we need
them to have those different semantic roles for situations like these.
Without them, we wouldn't be able to account for all of our
experience of the world, which includes a lot of luck and guessing.
Or rather, you could account for this kind of experience when
redefining our modes of accounting (remembering Pirsig's
endorsement of Einstein's slogan), but it would (so goes Rorty's side
of the bet) produce a bad kind of weirdness rather than a good kind.
In a lot of situations, so goes this semantic conception of language
and truth, it doesn't matter whether you say that a belief is justified
or true. But sometimes it does. It's the sometimes that a semantic
definition of truth attempts to codify.
Dave said:
Once you divest yourself of Platonic truth or get rid of the idea that
truth is about reality whereas opinions are about appearances, then
what could truth mean beyond this lived justification? Since your
analytic objection is predicated on the notion that truth and
justification can NOT be collapsed, I'd like to know why not? Why
doesn't that distinction collapse under the weight of anti-Platonism?
These are not rhetorical questions.
Matt:
"What could truth mean beyond this lived justification?" Why does
this sound like the collapse of truth _into_ justification, which you
slapped at me for as importing Platonism?
Aside from what seems like a razor-thin distinction on your part
between the way I put it and the way you put it, the one simple reason
why truth and justification cannot be collapsed is because of the
existence of the aforementioned "true beliefs that are not justified."
One certainly could reconstrue my belief that you are now holding a
Jack of Clubs as being justified by the mere fact that you are, but
this makes the point of Bain's definition of beliefs as guides to action
look weird (see the beginning of "What Pragmatism Means"). Would
it have been wise for me to be guided by my true belief that you
were holding the Jack of Spades (particularly as we find out now that
it was for very long)? It certainly may have so guided: we all know
that false beliefs guide action just as assuredly, if perhaps
occasionally disastrously (think: Iraq), as true beliefs. And some
false beliefs may have been justified at the time, which is why we
give them a pass morally, since while truth and justification may be
distinct, justification is still our only route to truth (a slogan I'm sure
I picked up from Rorty somewhere). But what about that true
belief? If the only thing going for it is a guess, should we say that
that's enough to guide an action? Don't we distinguish between
justified and unjustified beliefs just for these occasions, the
occasions in which the belief may end up true, but _experience_
has evolutionarily made it clear that mere guesses are typically not
a good guide to action?
I have three pieces that discuss pragmatism, truth, and Rorty.
"What Pragmatism Is" takes that annoying route that Rorty usually
takes, in playing up the "we shouldn't have a truth theory" angle. It
is a broad-view of what I take pragmatism to be.
http://pirsigaffliction.blogspot.com/2008/02/what-pragmatism-is.html
"Are There Bad Questions?" takes up an issue in interpreting Rorty,
outlining two of Rorty's rhetorical approaches, the
these-are-bad-questions approach and the I-have-no-theory
approach, using as its first example the famous passage from
Consequences of Pragmatism about theories of truth. (Apparently I
wrote this 7 months ago, though I'd forgotten. There's also an
addendum on Pirsig.)
http://pirsigaffliction.blogspot.com/2010/05/are-there-bad-questions.html
"Rhetorical Universalism" is an ambitious (i.e. perhaps still too
convoluted) attempt to talk about truth and belief by opposing a
Platonist and a Sophist. It works through a number of issues (like
Davidson, the rhetoric of illusion, the "all the way down" slogan
makes an appearance) that I think are in this area. I might put it for
the local audience as an attempt to answer Platt's favorite question
of "Is relativism absolutely true, or just relative?" in favor of Marsha
by paradoxically coopting the enemy's ism.
http://pirsigaffliction.blogspot.com/2010/05/rhetorical-universalism.html
Steve has a good discussion of pragmatism and truth in relationship
to theism here (there's also a series of responses I'm involved in
where I half-articulate some things about Davidson and the semantic
conception of truth):
http://www.atheistichope.com/2009/05/response-to-rc-sproul-on-pragmatism.html
Dave said:
"Epistemological behaviorism leaves no room for the kind of
practice-transcending legitimation that Rorty identifies as the defining
aspiration of modern epistemology." (from Ramberg's
plato.standford.edu entry on Rorty)
Steve said:
Can you give me an example of a constraint on knowledge claims
that is "practice-transcending"--one that isn't merely conversational?
Matt:
The true dilemma that faces Dave is this: Dave is going to want to
say "experience," because it is not obvious how this is "merely
conversational," but he is going to be uncomfortable because what
he means by "experience" is entirely pragmatic, the praxis of being
human, an experiencer of life. Dave will correctly see that his
discomfort comes from the fact that he's forced by the constraints of
Rorty's definition of what "epistemological behaviorism" is to reject
"merely conversational" this way. So Dave will object to Rorty's
definition of his own position as based on a false dilemma between
transcendence and conversation. However, since whatever Rorty's
notion of "conversation" is is based on its antithesis to
"practice-transcending legitimation," Dave has also made the target
of his animus invisible, since it only appears to us conceptually
_when_ and _only when_ it has "practice-transcending legitimation"
as its oppositional term. So the choice is 1) Dave can be
uncomfortable with Rorty or 2) by opposing "Jamesian experience"
to "Rortyan conversation," get Rorty wrong conceptually.
This is the kind of conceptual dilemma created by two different
vocabularies, only one of which you find rhetorically inviting. A third
way through is to ignore the offending vocabulary. If anybody asks,
you can say something pithy like, "Pirsigian experience is, too, a
rejection of 'practice-transcending legitimation,' however I don't like
Rorty's way of highlighting this as 'conversation.' I find the positive
project I want to build easier to do using 'experience' as my building
block, rather than 'language,' though there aren't a lot of conceptual
differences in what James and Pirsig do with 'experience' and Rorty
does with 'language.'" Perhaps there are some conceptual
differences down the line somewhere, but Rorty often worked at a
high metaphilosophical level of abstraction, and it hasn't become
any clearer to me--at that level--what those differences might be.
One can avoid Rorty's metaphilosophical vocabulary, and perhaps
bemoan the fact that he didn't come down the mountain more, but
I don't think there's a lot of traction to be had in deploying the
rhetoric of "denying" and "rejecting" to Rorty to convey these
differences.
Dave said:
I really don't understand this denial. I mean, doesn't Rorty explicitly
say that we to ought to give up on epistemology and truth theories?
Haven't you quoted him many times saying that?
Matt:
Shall I repeat to you the distinction between "saying" and "meaning"?
Matt
More information about the Moq_Discuss
mailing list