[MD] Rorty, Pirsig: Are There Bad Questions?
Matt Kundert
pirsigaffliction at hotmail.com
Thu May 20 16:28:49 PDT 2010
This is a post going up on my website (pirsigaffliction.blogspot.com)
tomorrow morning. It is split into two halves, the first about
Rorty, the second wondering about Pirsig. If you are curious
about Rorty, you might like the first part. If you are curious
about how Pirsig can be read in tandem with Rorty, you might
take a look at the second, which is completely detachable
from the first (and clearly demarcated below).
Are There Bad Questions?
Richard Rorty spent the last ten years of his life redacting
some
of his more controversial rhetorical strategies, which included
endlessly apologizing
for hyperbole. One of his favorite
strategies
was to say that there were bad questions: to pursue a certain line
of thought was to put yourself on the path to a conversational
cul-de-sac,
ending in aporia, a seeming inability
to get anybody to
agree to an answer.
This inability to find criteria that you could get people to agree on to
explain what a good answer would look like
was the tell-tale sign of a bad
question. The “bad question” approach
to
philosophical disagreement is hiding in his earliest writing, but began
to
truly flower when Rorty first formulated the groundplan for
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature in
1970 with “Cartesian
Epistemology and Changes in Ontology,” became solidified
in that
book, and most famously codified in the introduction to
Consequences of Pragmatism. In that intro, the bad-question
approach
becomes entwined with another strategy Rorty came to
embrace: the I-don’t-have-a-theory
approach. “[The pragmatist
theory of
truth] says that truth is not the sort of thing one should
expect to have a
philosophically interesting theory about” (CP xiii).
The ironic self-contradiction has always been plain to
people,
though most who have taken to pointing it out leave out the irony
and
what it means: the pragmatist theory of truth is one about why
we won’t have an
interesting theory about truth. That’s important,
though I’m not sure Rorty
always understood quite how important.
For a page later he says, famously:
“Pragmatists think that the history of attempts to isolate
the Truth
or the Good, or to define the word “true” or “good,” supports
their
suspicion that there is no interesting work to be done in this
area. It might, of course, have turned out otherwise. People have,
oddly enough, found something interesting to say about the
essence
of Force and the definition of “number.” They might have found
something interesting
to say about the essence of Truth. But
in fact
they haven’t. The history of
attempts to do so, and of criticisms of
such attempts, is roughly coextensive
with the history of that literary
genre we call “philosophy”—a genre founded by
Plato. So
pragmatists see the Platonic
tradition as having outlived its usefulness.
This does not mean they have a new, non-Platonic set of answers to
Platonic questions to offer, but rather that they do not think we
should ask
those questions anymore. When they
suggest that we
not ask questions about the nature of Truth and Goodness, they
do
not invoke a theory about the nature of reality or knowledge or man
which
says that “there is no such thing” as Truth or Goodness. Nor
do they have a “relativistic” or “subjectivist”
theory of Truth or
Goodness. They would
simply like to change the subject.” (CP xiv)
This “I have no theory” approach gets broadened into “and
neither
arguments nor theses,” as when he said in the late-70s,
“Non-Kantian
philosophers like Heidegger and Derrida are
emblematic figures who not only do
not solve problems, they do not
have
arguments or theses” (CP 93). This
eventually turns into his
claim that Contingency,
Irony, and Solidarity contains no
arguments (evidence to the contrary). The interrelationship between
what Rorty
means by “theory,” “argument,” and “thesis” at any given
moment can be parsed,
and I think it would show that it depends on
which direction he’s facing—whether
towards Platonists, who think
we must
have a theory, or towards pragmatists, who think they are
optional. This can be a complicated needle to thread
(principally
because it involves the fact
that people have, e.g., selves though
having a theory or thesis about that fact
is optional), but to make
the first pass in knitting the row, I would point out
that Rorty
doesn’t mention who finds
the essence of Force or definition of
“number” interesting. Because I certainly don’t. There are two
different audiences for “number”
and then “truth.” In the former
case,
the audience is likely mathematicians.
In the latter case,
Rorty’s audience is professional philosophers. And it is those who
disagree with how
interesting results about truth have been.
So
what does Rorty mean be “interesting”?
Rorty usually means by “interesting” in these contexts “discernable
effect on people’s lives.” In the case
of numbers, though
non-mathematicians could care less, the fact that
mathematics
professors do and keep producing results that pan out into the
warp of society means that the woof of what they do has interest.
This is not the case with “truth” and “good”
as of yet, for Rorty’s
claim is that inquiry into Truth has not helped people produce
more
true statements. And by and large (emphasis on the “large”)
this
is true. The trouble is that Rorty
has to admit that for philosophers,
inquiry into Truth has helped them
produce more true
statements—for example, Davidson’s claim that “most of our
beliefs
are true.” This, as Rorty
admits, is interesting and could not have
been done without the context of
logical positivism and their
unacknowledged Platonic goals.
Being forced to face this equivocation in his rhetorical
stances, Rorty
began to finally admit that he does have theses, or theories, or
pictures, of this or that philosophical-looking kind of object (“the
self” or “reality”
or “experience” or “language”). This
means a
disentangling of the bad-question approach and no-theory approach.
“I have no theory” is really code for “you
are going to be really
disappointed when I tell you what it is…,” and this
because of the
Platonic expectations typically carried by people asking for
one.
But this means that “bad question”
isn’t inherent, but rather a
conversational stability produced by the
instability of criteria for
what counts as a good answer. Rorty can
answer the question of
what truth is, but because of the wildly ranging
differences of
opinion over what it is good for, it will seem a bad answer to
somebody. The light in which Rorty’s answer, or anybody’s,
can
appear good is a stipulative light—“if for the moment we agree
on X, Y, and
Z, then this theory will satisfy it.” Rorty’s
stipulation
on truth has been the stipulation that truth, properly speaking
(which is to say “for the occasion of my theory”), is a semantic
and radically
non-epistemic concept. That is not the
only way we
use the word “true,” but
when push comes to shove, we should
stop trying to incorporate those uses, e.g.
the endorsing use, into
our theory of truth because doing so is what leads to
bad questions
that we can’t seem to answer, or would have any practical
consequences even if we could (like how we know when “snow is
white”
corresponds to the fact that snow is white). When Rorty
would say, “That’s a bad question
we shouldn’t ask,” he was
suggesting there might be other, more profitable
questions to
discuss. And when Rorty
gave an answer to the bad question, e.g.
a disquotational theory of truth, it
was intended shut down avenues
of thought that have proven interminable
cul-de-sacs (hence the
epithet for disquotationalists of “deflationists” and,
more generally
on Platonic questions, “quietists”).
Rorty had begun sorting out these equivocations and changes
in
stances in his last ten years, but in Rorty’s reply to Jaroslav
Peregrin in
his installment to the Living Library of Philosophers,
Rorty says most clearly
what I’ve articulated above (and what
produced the impetus to further
articulate this point on the scope
of his writing):
“I should also have been careful not to invoke Wittgenstein’s
contrast between “advancing theses” and “practicing therapy.”
Doing the former now seems to me a perfectly
legitimate, and
often useful, therapeutic technique. Peregrin cites Wittgenstein’s
claim that he
was “in a sense making propaganda for one style of
thinking as opposed to
another.” He says that this would be a
good description of my preferred mode of philosophical activity.
I am happy to accept the suggestion, but less
happy about this
suggestion that “neither Wittgenstein nor Rorty thinks that it
is
possible to give a theory answering ‘philosophical questions’.”
“Consider Davidson’s thesis that most of our beliefs must be
true,
or Brandom’s inferentialist theory about the origin of singular
terms.
Such theses and theories provide
answers to questions like, “Well,
what will we say about the relation between
language and
nonlanguage, once we abandon the familiar ‘realist’ account?” By
providing the pragmatist with such
answers, they facilitate his
propagandizing efforts. Not everybody feels it necessary to pose
such
questions seriously, but when somebody does it is nice to be
able to gratify
her. Though sometimes it works best to
say, “that’s
a bad question, one that we pragmatists don’t ask,” with some
interlocutors it is more effective to reply, “here’s an answer to that
question, since you insist on asking it.” (The
Philosophy of Richard Rorty 247-8)
If I had to speculate on what most produced this change in
Rorty,
I would have to say it was the work of his student, Robert Brandom.
Rorty grew up, philosophically speaking, on
Davidson, who was at
Princeton for a time in the late 60s. Rorty spent much of the 60s
retooling as an
analytic philosopher, which meant falling in love with
Sellars and becoming
acquainted with Davidson’s cast of mind.
Rorty was left to his own devices after Davidson left, and the
formative
70s—when Rorty was drawing out the consequences of
Sellars, Quine, and Davidson—were
also the years Brandom was
at Princeton, ’72-’77.
Rorty’s fall from analytic-grace was initially a souring
with “system,”
with the hopes of pay-off attending all the work that must be
done
to create a system. Rorty was first
and foremost a voracious reader,
and he loved reading systems in the hopes
there has a hidden source
of power in them (he wrote his master’s thesis and
dissertation on
Whitehead). In the end,
I think Rorty liked reading too
much—sitting
at a desk, pouring energy into getting the system just
right, didn’t seem
appealing because it took him out of the library
stacks too long (or away from
the forests where he loved bird-watching).
And combine this with his reading of so many systems, whether
Kant’s or
Hegel’s or Carnap’s or Whitehead’s (or Dewey’s, for
that matter), all claiming
to have the hiddern power, and all of them
contradicting each other, and you
have a recipe for someone with a
pretty good self-justification for not writing
a system himself.
Rorty’s disagreement
with Davidson throughout his career pretty
much amounts to the fact that
Davidson always wanted to write a
system, but never got around to it—so Rorty would always wonder
about the
aspiration, since the work he was doing in essays was so
good itself. Brandom, however, is a brilliant
systematizer, and has
done in Making It
Explicit what Davidson was never able to do
and Rorty never thought worth
doing. From the time of that book’s
publication in 1994, you can see a slow slide in Rorty’s responses
to Brandom,
beginning with a queasy reaction to his rehabilitiation
of “representation” to
a final “I still don’t think regular people need
a system, but if you want one,
get a load of this…totally worth it.”
----------
Addendum on Pirsig
What does Pirsig think about bad questions and systems?
I think it’s important to notice the course of events and
presentation.
In ZMM, Pirsig describes the S/O Dilemma as an aporia created by
a previous agreement on the terms of debate. Pirsig later describes
“truth traps,” on the
analogy of the “old South Indian Monkey
Trap”—which is similar to Chinese
finger-cuffs—and interprets the
Japenese word “mu” as “unask the question.”
And then ZMM ends
(there’s a chance I might be forgetting
something). The trick is that Pirsig offers a few
half-hearted stabs
at sysematizing his thoughts about Quality (don’t forget the
diagram
in Ch. 20), but the point of the story doesn’t appear to be a
replacement system, but rather the resurrection of Phaedrus after
chasing down the
ghost of reason to Plato. When we move
to
Lila, I think we should pay close
attention to how the Metaphysics
of Quality is introduced. Pirsig quickly presents us with the
quandry
of SOM, a sort of recapitulation of the point of ZMM,
and begins to describe his metaphysical answers. What happens
then is that Rigel intercedes
and objects (Ch. 6). Pirsig then
bemoans
his answers given, and the problem turns out to be a
pernicious understanding
of virtue—Pirsig let Rigel and the
Victorians decide the terms of debate (the
definition of the terms)
and so lost before the fight even began.
The Metaphysics of Quality takes flight after a
conversational
difficulty. Pirsig writes
that Phaedrus “realized that sooner or later
he was going to have to stop
carping about how bad subject-object
metaphysics was and say something positive
for a change” (Lila
123, Ch. 9). Why? Because
“he had already violated the
nothingness of mystic reality” (124), he’d already
said something
positive rather than sticking to the via negativa that mystics,
particularly in the West, typically
force themselves to stick to, a
route that after Hegel (and particularly
Adorno) became more and
more prominent in non-theological metaphysics, too. Pirsig
realizes that he has to say something,
even that saying things are
good. And
this is where the presentation is interesting.
The two
paragraphs run like this:
“By even using the term “Quality” he had already violated
the
nothingness of mystic reality. The
use of the term “Quality” set up
a pile of questions of its own that have
nothing to do with mystic
reality and walks away leaving them unaswered. Even the name,
“Quality,” was a kind of
definition since it tended to associate
mystic reality with certain fixed and
limited understandings.
Already he was
in trouble. Was the mystic reality of
the universe
really more immanent in the higher-priced cuts of meat in the
butcher
shop? These were “Quality” meants weren’t
they? Was
the butcher using the term
incorrectly? Phaedrus had no answers.
. . . [ellipsis Pirsig’s] That was the problem this morning
too, with
Rigel. Phaedrus had no
answers. If you’re going to talk about
Quality at all you have to be ready to answer someone like Rigel.
You have to have a ready-made Metaphysics of
Quality that you
can snap at him like some catechism. Phaedrus didn’t have a
Catechism of Quality
and that’s why he got hit.” (124)
Pirsig considers metaphysics to be a good thing to do
because it
gives you an answer to people like Rigel, people who insist on
certain questions. The analogy with
Catholic practices in
particular highlights what Pirsig has in mind. “Catechism” is from
Greek roots that mean an “indoctrination.” This has bad
connotations to our ears now, as
does the other name Catholics
have for it: dogma. But all Pirsig is highlighting is how what he
is
lacking is a systematic way to keep things straight in his line of
thought,
and how to answer people who press him.
Pirsig immediately goes on to analogize metaphysics with
chess,
and writes this:
“Trying to create a perfect metaphysics is like trying to
create a
perfect chess strategy, one that will win every time. You can’t do
it. It’s out of the range of human
capability. No matter what
position you
take on a metaphysical question someone will always
start asking questions that
will lead to more positions that lead to
more questions in this endless
intellectual chess game. The game
is
supposed to stop when it is agreed that a particular line of
reasoning is
illogical. This is supposed to be
similar to a checkmate.
But conflicting
positions go on for centuries without any such
checkmate being agreed upon.”
(125)
I’m not sure Pirsig ever comments further on the purpose of
this
paragraph. But we might notice that
Pirsig’s subsumption of
“reasonable” to “good” from ZMM should still be in effect, which
may explain why “illogic” does
not always hold sway. And further,
we
might imagine that Pirsig did have
his Catechism of Quality at
the ready when Rigel comes calling—would Rigel have
been
blown away? Should he have? There is no
indication in these
early pages, and particularly with the above paragraph,
that Pirsig
believes that had Phaedrus the MoQ ready to snap, it would have
changed Rigel’s mind. It would have,
rather, continued the
conversation (until, perhaps, Rigel tired out
first). Consider, too,
the fact that
when Rigel returns at the close, there’s no indication
that any of Phaedrus’ “answers”
are what lead Rigel to come back
(for more on this curious aspect see my “Prospectus” http://pirsigaffliction.blogspot.com/2006/04/prospectus-for-idiosyncratic-and.html).
What sometimes gets lost in metaphysical system-building is
the
person doing the building, and what the building is for. For Pirsig,
there is a strong indication that
metaphysics is for keeping yourself
straight in conversation—consider Pirsig’s
introduction to Lila’s
Child where he
picks up the chess metaphor again and says that
“real chess is the game you
play with your neighors. Real chess is
‘muddling
through.’ Real chess is the triumph of
mental organization
over complex experience.
And so is real philosophy” (viii).
“Muddling through” is one of Dewey’s favorite images, one that
Rorty
loved to promote. Between Pirsig’s
lament about getting
broad-sided by Rigel and the Catechism of Quality, there’s
Pirsig’s
chapter on metaphysical platypi—the outcome of previously made
cuts in
the metaphysical firmament, previously made choices about
which questions
deserve answers. Pirsig says early in
that chapter
that “saying that a Metaphysics of Quality is false and a
subject-object metaphysics is true is like saying that rectangular
coordinates
are true and polar coordinates are false” (Lila
115,
Ch. 8). Both are used, are
determined better or worse, relative to
the purpose with which you are using
them. The figure standing
there weighing
the options between the two alternatives is the
philosopher, who sometimes goes
missing in the attempt to limn
the structure of reality.
And if someone insists
on asking whether Quality is in the subject
or object? Just say, “both—the object’s made out of
inorganic,
and maybe biological static patterns of Quality, and for the subject
just tack on some intellectual and/or social static patterns of Quality.”
And then you have your answer to a bad
question. The questions
won’t stop, but
do they ever?
_________________________________________________________________
The New Busy is not the too busy. Combine all your e-mail accounts with Hotmail.
http://www.windowslive.com/campaign/thenewbusy?tile=multiaccount&ocid=PID28326::T:WLMTAGL:ON:WL:en-US:WM_HMP:042010_4
More information about the Moq_Discuss
mailing list